University of Memphis University of Memphis
University of Memphis Digital Commons University of Memphis Digital Commons
Electronic Theses and Dissertations
4-16-2024
DEATH OF THE SUBJECT: HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT ON DEATH OF THE SUBJECT: HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT ON
SUBJECT AND SUBJECTIVITY SUBJECT AND SUBJECTIVITY
Qiuyue Chen
Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.memphis.edu/etd
Recommended Citation Recommended Citation
Chen, Qiuyue, "DEATH OF THE SUBJECT: HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT ON SUBJECT AND SUBJECTIVITY"
(2024).
Electronic Theses and Dissertations
. 3533.
https://digitalcommons.memphis.edu/etd/3533
This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by University of Memphis Digital Commons. It has been
accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of University of
Memphis Digital Commons. For more information, please contact khgger[email protected].
DEATH OF THE SUBJECT: HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT ON SUBJECT AND
SUBJECTIVITY
By
Qiuyue Chen
A Thesis
Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the
Requirements for the Degree of
Master of Arts
Major: Philosophy
The University of Memphis
May 2024
ii
Abstract
The discourse on subjectivity, a central theme in philosophy, has garnered attention from
thinkers like Heidegger and Foucault. Heidegger critiques subjectivity through a lens of
metaphysics and ontology, while Foucault examines it as a social construct. This thesis aims to
analyze their critiques and find common ground. The first chapter delves into Heidegger's
critique of Cartesian subject and subject-object dualism in Being and Time and Being and Truth,
arguing it obstructs a comprehensive understanding of human existence. In the second chapter,
Foucault's analysis of subjectification, notably in The History of Sexuality, illustrates how the
process of subjectification shapes self-knowledge and identities. The third chapter compares
Heidegger’s and Foucault's perspectives, highlighting shared insights into subjectivity's historical
and philosophical dimensions.
iii
Table of Contents:
Chapter
Page
Abstract ii
Introduction iii
Chapter 1: Heidegger’s Critique of the Cartesian Subject and Metaphysics 1
Chapter 2: Foucault’s Critique of Subjectification—Subjectivity and Truth Effect 16
Chapter 3: The Mathematical in Heidegger and the Cartesian Moment in Foucault 27
References 35
iv
Introduction:
The discourse surrounding subjectivity has long been a central debate in the history of
philosophy, with thinkers like Heidegger and Foucault offering unique perspectives and
critiques on the concept of the subject. Heidegger's approach to critiquing the subject stems
from his broader examination of the history of metaphysics and ontology, while Foucault
presents a groundbreaking critique by analyzing the subject as a social and historical construct.
This thesis aims to elucidate these philosophers' critiques of the concept of the subject and
explore common ground to bridge their analyses and thoughts on subjectivity.
In the first chapter, the problematic nature of the concept of the subject for Heidegger
will be illuminated. In his seminal work, Being and Time and his lecture course, Being and
Truth, Heidegger launches a profound critique of the Cartesian subject. He challenges the
dualistic separation between the subject and the world, arguing that it impedes a comprehensive
understanding of human existence. Heidegger contends that the Cartesian subject perpetuates a
'subject-object' dualism, hindering a holistic grasp of our Being.
The second chapter will delineate Foucault's exposition of the process of
subjectification in the construction of sexuality and its impact on individuals' self-knowledge.
Foucault's exploration, particularly evident in The History of Sexuality, delves into the intricate
dynamics of subjectification, especially concerning sexuality, knowledge, and truth. He reveals
how societal power structures employ knowledge and truth to mold individuals' identities and
behaviors.
v
In the third chapter, a historical perspective will be adopted to demonstrate why
Foucault and Heidegger can be compared regarding their thoughts on subjectivity. Heidegger's
analysis of the role played by the concept of the subject in the history of metaphysics shares
significant common ground with Foucault's examination of the influence of the Cartesian
moment on the history of subjectivity and truth.
1
Chapter One: Heidegger’s Critique of the Cartesian Subject and Metaphysics
Heidegger has posited significant criticisms of traditional metaphysics and has carefully
reexamined some of its fundamental concepts. One of the critical metaphysical concepts is the
subject that traditional metaphysics usually identifies with the human self, especially since
Descartes. In this chapter, I will first explicate Heidegger’s critiques of the Cartesian
metaphysical system, focusing on the reason why he finds the concept of the subject problematic
and his criticism of the Cartesian dualism between subject and object. Then I will delve into
Heidegger’s phenomenological interpretation of “knowing” and demonstrate how it dismantles
the Cartesian metaphysical system, especially the dualism between subject and object.
Criticism of the Cartesian Metaphysical System
Descartes proposes the argument "ego cogito, ergo sum"
1
in his Principles of Philosophy,
which translates to "I think, therefore I am"
2
in English. He proves this statement by arguing that
as long as I am doubting, there must exist an “I” who is doubting. Doubting is one kind of
thinking, so “I” who is doubting is also thinking. Hence, the “I” who is thinking cannot be
questioned away by radical doubt. Therefore, “I” who is thinking must exist.
Heidegger criticizes the notion of the “I” derived from the argument “ego cogito, ergo
sum,
3
eventually becomes a mere “thing.” Moreover, he contends that the Cartesian “I” distracts
us from understanding the human self. To illustrate Heidegger’s critique, I will explain it in three
steps.
1
Descartes René, The Principles of Philosophy, trans. Jonathan Bennett (Charlottesville, VA: InteLex, n.d.)., part 1,
article 7
2
Ibid.
3
Ibid.
2
Firstly, Heidegger points out that Descartes’s radical doubt rests on the presumption that
the most certain ground for philosophy and knowledge must be absolutely simple. Since by
engaging in the methodical doubt, we suspect that everything related to sensual perceptions and
extended bodies is an unreal illusion, Descartes seeks certainty which cannot be doubted even in
the most extreme scenario where we cannot even trust our thoughts due to the possibility of
being deceived by an evil genius. Through this methodical doubting process, Descartes actually
looks for the most perspicuous and indubitable thing that is present-at-hand to serve as
fundamentum for philosophy. What is present-at-hand, for Heidegger, is when an entity is taken
out of its background or context, totally deprived of its significance in terms of practical usage as
an equipment. Then this entity stands as absolutely independent or isolated object, merely
bearing some generic attributes such as weight and height, devoid of any contextual relevance.
By “ego cogito, ergo sum,
4
what finally has survived through the methodical doubt is the most
indubitable ground ego cogito.” As Descartes engages in the process of radical doubt to
discern the thinking “I,” it resembles bringing this very “I” into focus and scrutinization. Every
image, sound, color, memory and associated aspect of this “I” that cannot pass the test of radical
doubt is discarded. What remains is solely the “I” who is thinking, laid bare before scrutiny. This
thinking “I,” emerging from the crucible of radical doubt, becomes phenomenologically removed
from the settings of everydayness. Thus the thinking “I” also has the mode of Being-present-at-
hand. That is, “I” who thinks is the most indubitable and perspicuous presence-at-hand.
Heidegger argues that in Western philosophy our understanding of the human self is
mainly shaped by the Cartesian notion of the “I,” stemming from the famous argument “ego
4
Descartes, Principle of Philosophy, Part 1, Article 7
3
cogito, ergo sum”
5
. Furthermore, the Cartesian “I” has subsequently become linked to the
concept of “subject.” Heidegger writes, “…the conception of the human self was pointed in a
certain direction by the Cartesian thought of the I: through Descartes, the I is really made into the
subject, and it has been called the subject since then.”
6
The reasons are as follows. According to
Heidegger, the term “subjectum” originated from the Greek word, “ποκεμενον
7
initially
designates “everything that already lies before us in advance that we run into and come upon.”
8
In other words, subjectum indicates something that lies outside of us and is already present
before us as given.
To understand the connection between subjectum and the human self, we must
understand how subjectum relates to Cartesian I. Based on the process of methodical doubt I just
analyzed, the Cartesian I, which survives through the process of the methodical doubt, is exactly
something indubitable and simple presence-to-us as proximally given. Thus, the properties of
Cartesian I match the definition of subjectum, which is, in other words, something that lies in
front of us as given. Therefore, the concept of Cartesian I falls within the scope of the subjectum.
At the same time, since the indubitable thinking “I” gains its fundamental status in the Cartesian
metaphysical system, serving as the most certain ground (or fundamentum) for all knowledge,
the “I” originated from “ego cogito” is not just another subjectum but the essential subjectum.
Hence, the Cartesian I is the most fundamental presence-at-hand. Therefore, Heidegger
5
Descartes, Principle of Philosophy, Part 1, Article 7
6
Martin Heidegger, Being and Truth, trans. Gregory Fried and Richard Polt (Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 2016), 34.
7
Hypokeimenon, usually translated as material substratum, meaning the “underlying thing” in metaphysics
8
Heidegger, Being and Truth, 35
4
concludes that “the I is a subjectum in the old sense…the subjectum is originally ‘I.’”
9
Moreover,
since “subject” designates “the preeminent subjectum,”
10
“subject” then refers to the “I.”
However, when we say “I,” this “I” also refers to ourselves, as Heidegger reveals, “but first of
all, for the individual human being, the I means what he himself is, that within which he has his
self as his own.”
11
Thus, when I utter “I,” I also indicate my own self. However, the “I” related to
“subject” now appears as something present-at-hand like something we happen upon and
encounter.
Therefore, we arrive at the final equation of subject as I as self, “self-qua-I as subjectum:
something present at hand.”
12
As we have analyzed earlier, the Cartesian I endowed with the
feature of presence-at-hand as the “subject,” ultimately makes the human self look like a thing.
In order to grasp the full image of Heidegger’s critique of Cartesian subject, it is essential to fully
understand what the term “thing” means. As to “thing”, Heidegger, in his 1927 Being and Time
(henceforth BT) talks about the ontological meaning of this term. According to Heidegger, a
“thing” is that to which its own Being does not matter. In other words, as for “things,” they are
indifferent about their own Being, and the question of Being does not matter to them. Thus, “I”
as the subject which appears as a thing is problematic for Heidegger. Through the concept of the
subject, we can never get into the question of Being. Heidegger writes, “Thus Dasein is never to
be taken ontologically as an instance or special case of some genus of entities as things that are
present-at-hand. To entities such as these, their Being is ‘a matter of indifference’; or more
9
Heidegger, Being and Truth, 35
10
Ibid.
11
Heidegger, Being and Truth, 33-34
12
Ibid., 35
5
precisely, they ‘are’ such that their Being can be neither a matter of indifference to them, nor the
opposite.”
13
To gain insight into the concept of “thing,” Heidegger gives an account of its
character of Being, including “substantiality, materiality, extendedness, side-by-side-ness.”
14
It is
the reason why Heidegger criticizes, “the thing-character of the I and self is not overcome as
long as its subject-character is not removed in advance, that is, as long as the fatefulness of the
Cartesian approach is not grasped and overcome from the bottom up.”
15
Additionally, the argument ego cogito, ergo sum
16
implies that this “I” knows itself as a
thinking thing. Since when I am thinking, I become aware that this I who is thinking is
something of certainty. It’s this awareness of thinking I reflected back to the I who is thinking
during the process of radical doubt finally confirms the existence of the “I.” Consequently,
Descartes' “cogito, ergo sum” endows the self with the essential attribute of self-consciousness.
Heidegger asserts that the essence of the self is primarily evident in consciousness.
17
Since the
radical doubt has turned down all things except the thinking “I” and its awareness of itself, this
“self-consciousness” becomes so significant to the Cartesian “I” that the Being of human self
becomes “self-consciousness.” However, this leads to another nocuous consequence: The Being
of the human self has already been presupposed by Descartes’s “ego cogito.” Self-consciousness
as the Being of the self is all that we know. Heidegger points out, “In accordance with the
priority of the I-qua-consciousness, consciousness determines the essence of Being. That of
13
Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (New York: Harper Perennial
Modern Classics, 2008), 42/68.
14
BT, 68/96
15
Heidegger, Being and Truth, 36
16
Descartes, Principle of philosophy, Part 1, Article 7
17
Heidegger, Being and Truth, 34
6
which one is conscious, in a particular mode of mathematical indubitability, ‘is’and this
consciousness is genuine Being.
18
Therefore, the conception of the self as "Being-conscious"
19
cannot answer important questions, such as how the self is connected with others, how it exists in
the world, and how it evolves over time and throughout history. For Heidegger, these questions
are essential for understanding the human self, which understanding the Cartesian I fails to
achieve. Therefore, Heidegger criticizes the Cartesian I as the "failure to reach the authentic self
of man."
20
and “it obstructs in all possible ways every path to the human self.”
21
In conclusion, Descartes builds up his metaphysical system by exploring the
epistemological question of how we can know this world truly and build our knowledge from a
certain ground. His famous argument, “ego cogito ergo sum,” establishes the fundamentum of
philosophy on the certitude of thinking “I” and at the same time provides his answer of “to be” as
being a thinking thingthat is, the subject. Descartes builds up the relationship between
knowers and the outside world as the dualism between the subject and object. Furthermore, the
understanding of the human self is transformed into the subject as something present-at-hand.
However, Heidegger challenges this dualism by arguing that the relation between the subject and
object can never be the same as the Dasein and the world. Based on previous analysis, equating
Dasein with the subject is also wrong for Heidegger. Çüçen also stresses that “For Heidegger, the
interpretation of the present-at-hand of Dasein is illegitimate because this interpretation is based
18
Ibid., 36
19
Ibid.
20
Heidegger, Being and Truth, 35
21
Ibid., 36
7
on the epistemological attitude of ‘res cogito’ who knows and interprets itself as a present-at-
hand.”
22
Moreover, there seems to be a gap between the subject and the external world in the
Cartesian metaphysical system. Çüçen points out, “the consequence of the spirit of Descartes’
philosophy separates the ideal inner world of the subject from the outer world of the object. The
subject is divorced from the world and the world is put out ‘there’ as separate from the
subject.”
23
This divide is connected by one major activityknowing. Through the process of
knowing, the subject transcends itself, goes into the outside world, and grasps things within this
external world. Heidegger perceives this knowing procedure as “a subject provides itself with
representations of something which remain stored up 'inside' as having been thus appropriated,
and with regard to which the question of how they ‘agree’ with actuality can occasionally
arise.”
24
Thus, Heidegger raises questions concerning this internalized subject and its knowing
process,
“how this knowing subject comes out of its inner 'sphere' into one which is 'other and
external’; how knowing can have any object at all; and how one must think of the object
itself so that eventually the subject knows it without needing to venture a leap into
another sphere.”
25
In order to reach the external world, the subject as the knower and the external world as
something to be known is bridged by Descartes’ “ego cogito.” The subject is certain of one
22
A. Kadir Çüçen, “Heidegger’s Reading of Descartes’ Dualism,The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress
of Philosophy, 1998: 62, https://doi.org/10.5840/wcp20-paideia19986134.
23
Çüçen, “Heidegger’s Reading of Descartes’ Dualism”, 58
24
BT, 62/89
25
BT, 60/87
8
thing: “I think” and I think my thoughts. Since I am certain that I am thinking, these objects that
I am thinking of enter into the inner world of the thinking subject as representations and thus also
gain the certitude as representations of the outer world. However, the external world still seems
afar. All these objects in the external world only get certified as representations in the content of
the thinking “I” and the outside world is regarded as images brought into the inner world of the
thinking “I. These objects in the outer world only have limited certitude depending on the
thinking subject, and hence this “I” seems isolated. Çüçen also states this issue of Descartes’
metaphysics, “as the ground of this metaphysics, the existent lies as present in front of us, as a
representation in which the subject gets the certainty of things. In the metaphysics of Descartes,
the existent is defined as objectivity of representation and truth is defined as the certitude of
representation.”
26
Another issue Heidegger raises is that Descartes, in his argument “Cogito ergo sum,”
confuses the meaning of “I am” with “I think” without first figuring out the ontological
significance of “Sum,” which refers to “to be” or “to exist.” Heidegger succinctly indicates this
problem in SZ, stating, “with the ‘cogito sum’ Descartes had claimed that he was putting
philosophy on a new and firm footing. But what he left undetermined when he began in this
'radical' way, was the kind of Being which belongs to the res cogitans, or more precisely the
meaning of the Being of the ‘sum.’”
27
Shockey points out, “But what he left undetermined with
this ‘‘radical’’ beginning, was the way of being of the res cogitans, ormore preciselythe
meaning of the being of the ‘sum’ (BT: 24/46). In other words, Heidegger claims that Descartes
shifts our attention to subjectivity, to the entity we each are, but without then properly asking
26
Çüçen, “Heidegger’s Reading of Descartes’ Dualism”, 61
27
BT, 25/46
9
what it is to be such an entity, and, a fortiori, without asking what connection our being has with
being in general.”
28
Thus, according to Heidegger’s reading of Descartes, knowing is merely a
dichotomous relation between the subject and the object. However, this dichotomous structure is
presupposed without knowing the ontological nature of these entities. Heidegger writes, “So in
this way it becomes the ‘evident’ point of departure for problems of epistemology or the
‘metaphysics of knowledge’. For what is more obvious than that a ‘subject’ is related to an
‘Object’ and vice versa? This ‘subject-object-relationship’ must be presupposed. But while this
presupposition is unimpeachable in its facticity, this makes it indeed a baleful one, if its
ontological necessity and especially its ontological meaning are to be left in the dark.”
29
I. Destruction of Cartesian Dualism of Subject and Object
Heidegger came up with his phenomenological project of Dasein. Dasein is the being that
takes its own Being as an issue. Heidegger emphasizes that it is different from the analysis of
Descartes’ “ego cogito.” Dasein cannot be reduced to the “ego cogito” or the subject. He warns
against this reduction stating “if we posit an ‘I’ or subject as that which is proximally given, we
shall completely miss the phenomenal content [Bestand] of Dasein.”
30
Heidegger comes up with
Dasein to answer the fundamental question of the meaning of Being. According to Heidegger,
terms like subject, consciousness, and spirit cannot fulfil this task. All empirical sciences are
inadequate to provide satisfactory answers too as Heidegger writes, “the subject, the soul, the
consciousness, the spirit, the person. All these terms refer to definite phenomenal domains which
can be ‘given form’: but they are never used without a notable failure to see the need for
28
R. Matthew Shockey, “Heidegger’s Descartes and Heidegger’s Cartesianism,” European Journal of Philosophy
20, no. 2 (2010): 288, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0378.2010.00408.x.
29
BT, 59/86
30
BT, 46/72
inquiring about the Being of the entities thus designated”
31
and “In suggesting that anthropology,
psychology, and biology all fail to give an unequivocal and ontologically adequate answer to the
question about the kind of Being which belongs to those entities which we ourselves are.”
32
Dasein is an ideal starting point for exploring the question of the meaning of Being. As
Heidegger points out, Dasein has a crucial feature of “mineness”. Essentially, Dasein is always
“mine” since it is an entity that considers its own Being as an issue in its Being. Heidegger notes,
“Dasein has in each case mineness, one must always use a personal pronoun when one addresses
it: ‘I am’, ‘you are’.”
33
Furthermore, Dasein always conducts itself towards its Being in one way
or the other in its existence, which makes this entity “mine” as Heidegger indicates, “in each case
Dasein is mine to be in one way or another. Dasein has always made some sort of decision as to
the way in which it is in each case mine.”
34
Additionally, Dasein cares about its own Being in its
existence, as evidenced by this statement “Dasein is an entity which in each case I myself am.
Mineness belongs to any existent Dasein.”
35
Thus, Dasein becomes the main focus of
Heidegger’s project of existential analysis different from the subject, the person, and the spirit,
and we will explore how this project sheds light upon the human existence and human self.
According to Heidegger, Dasein's fundamental state of Being is known as “Being-in-the-
world.” He explains that "Being-in-the-world" is an "existentiale with a plural form known as
"existentialia", which represents the characters of Dasein's Being. These characters can only be
31
BT, 46/72
32
BT, 50/75
33
BT, 42/68
34
BT, 42/68
35
BT, 53/78
discovered through the existence of Dasein. As such, this state of Being cannot be understood as
one thing being inside another thing, like presence-at-hand. Heidegger explains this basic state of
DaseinBeing-in-the-world from an etymological angle. The word “in” originates from
“innan,” meaning “to reside or dwell,” and “An” means “‘I am accustomed,’ ‘I am familiar
with,’ ‘I look after something.’”
36
Hence, “innan” implies “to reside or dwell” and “I care for
something.” In German, “bin” translates to “am,” and “bin” is related to “bei,” so Heidegger
concludes “‘ich bin’ (‘I am’) means in its turn ‘I reside’ or ‘dwell alongside’ the world, as that
which is familiar to me in such and such a way.”
37
Moreover, Dasein with its major characteristic
of mineness is always “I am.” And “Being” is the infinitive of “ich bin” (“I am”) so Being-in
finally designates that “to dwell alongside the world”
38
and “to be familiar with the world in
some ways.”
39
Thus, “Being-in is thus the formal existential expression for the Being of
Dasein.”
40
With a solid grasp of Being-in, we can better understand knowing as a state of Being of
Dasein. Unlike Descartes who establishes the metaphysical system from the epistemological
relation between the knower and the outside world as representations, Heidegger constructs
Dasein which obliterates the gap between the subject and the object, the knower and the outside
world. Knowing, according to Heidegger, is the prime exemplifier of Being-in-the-world. He
asserts that Dasein is already and beforehand familiar with Being-in-the-world, as supported by
36
BT, 54/80
37
BT, 54/80
38
BT, 54/80
39
Ibid.
40
Ibid.
his statement that “Being-in-the-world is something of which one has pre-phenomenological
experience and acquaintance.”
41
This state of Being can always be observed in every Dasein as it
constitutes every aspect of Dasein’s existence. Heidegger explains that Being-in-the-world
“makes up a basic state of Dasein, and in every case is already disclosed for Dasein's
understanding of Being, and disclosed along with that Being itself.”
42
This can be further
illustrated by the fact that Being-in-the-world has manifested in various specific examples of
Dasein’s existence like noticing something, paying attention and caring about something, making
and using something, talking, considering, and deciding. Thus, Being-in-the-world is not just a
mere character added upon Dasein, which can be dispensable, but an existential expression of
Dasein’s Being. Heidegger emphasizes, “Being-in is not a ‘property’ which Dasein sometimes
has and sometimes does not have, and without which it could be just as well as it could with it. It
is not the case that man 'is' and then has, by way of an extra, a relationship-of-Being towards the
'world'-a world with which he provides himself occasionally. Dasein is never ‘proximally’ an
entity which is, so to speak, free from Being-in.”
43
We have to understand Being-in-the-world phenomenologically as an essential state of
Dasein’s Being. A significant way of Being-in-the-world is committing oneself to the world and
discussing it, which is known as “Being-in-the-world which knows”
44
according to Heidegger,
the ontical interpretation of the phenomenon of knowing merely as a relationship between two
entities is subject to criticism. Dreyfus also points out, “…nor contemplative knowing can be
41
BT, 59/86
42
BT, 59/85
43
BT, 57/84
44
BT, 60/87
understood as a relation between a self-sufficient mind and an independent world…Knowing the
world is a founded mode of being-in. Knowing is an exemplary subject/object relation, so that if
one makes knowing basic, one is from the start locked into the intentionalistic picture of human
beings as subjects with beliefs (justified and unjustified) about objects and states of affairs.”
45
To
fully grasp the meaning of knowing as a founded mode of Being-in, we need to find out the
Being of this knowing, which I conclude can be expressed in two words: "inside" and "outside".
As for “inside”, in Heidegger’s words, we have to notice that “knowing has the phenomenal
character of a Being which is in and towards the world.”
46
This means that as a modality of
Being-in-the-world, knowing is already “inside” the world in the sense that it is concerned about
the world in which it exists. Since the essence of Being-in-the-world is concern, it is naturally
drawn to the world that it is concerned about. Hence, as a mode of Dasein founded upon Being-
in-the-world, knowing is already “in” and towards the world. When it comes to the concept of
“outside,” it's important to remind ourselves again that Dasein's primary state of Being is Being-
in-the-world, which is inherently concerned with the world around it. This means that Dasein has
already situated itself "outside" and alongside the entities within the world, rather than dwelling
solely within its inner world.
Additionally, it's worth noting that Dasein doesn't need to transcend an inner "castle" in
order to understand and interact with the outside world, as might be the case in a Cartesian
metaphysical system. This new perspective requires us to analyze the process of knowing from a
phenomenological angle, rather than an epistemological angle of dualism between subject and
45
Hubert L. Dreyfus, Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, Division I (Cambridge.
Mass. u.a.: MIT Press, 2009). 49
46
BT, 60/87
object as prescribed by Descartes. Heidegger emphasizes, “knowing is grounded beforehand in a
Being-already-alongside-the-world, which is essentially constitutive for Dasein's Being.”
47
Zimmerman also emphasize that, “Experiences which are normally regarded as "inner" or
"subjective" are entirely worldly; they are part of my worldly experience. Even my experience of
myself as a conscious subject is a worldly experience, for I cannot escape the world: I am always
in the world of my experience. The world is not a collection of objects outside of me, and my
self is not a bundle of ideas and feelings inside of me.”
48
Heidegger’s approach to knowing is phenomenological, where he initially considers
knowing as a means of understanding the nature of something present-at-hand through
observation. However, he also emphasizes that when Being-in-the-world as concern removes
itself from any production or manipulation, it transforms into another form of Being of Dasein
which is Being-towards-the-world which just looks at entities as the way they are. In this mode,
Dasein can direct its sight at what is present-at-hand. Heidegger suggests that this mode of
looking becomes a mode of Being alongside entities within-the-world, which he refers to as
“dwelling autonomously alongside entities within-the-world.”
49
Through this dwelling, Dasein
has completed “the perception of the present-at-hand”
50
which involves addressing oneself
towards something present-at-hand and then discussing it. According to Heidegger, a broad sense
of interpretation has been consummated through this process of perception, which is “an act of
47
BT, 61/88
48
Michael E. Zimmerman, Eclipse of the Self: The Development of Heidegger’s Concept of Authenticity (Ohio:
Ohio University Press, 1986), 27.
49
BT, 61/89
50
BT, 62/89
making determinate.”
51
Since knowing, as defined by Heidegger, is a process of making
determinate of the nature of something present-at-hand, we just accomplished a
phenomenological description of this process of knowing. Thus, knowing is to be regarded
phenomenologically as Being-in-the-world that knows, and it dwells alongside entities in the
world that are to be known. Heidegger concludes that knowing cannot be construed as a mere
procedural act in which a subject acquires representations that are stored internally, waiting to be
compared to reality on occasion. He emphasizes that perceiving what is known isn't akin to
retrieving acquired "booty" and placing it within the confines of consciousness. Even in the acts
of perceiving, retaining, and preserving knowledge, the knowing Dasein remains outside of
consciousness and in the world, existing as Dasein. Thus, by creating Dasein and presenting a
positive description of the phenomenon of Dasein’s knowing, Heidegger bridges the chasm
between the inner world of the subject and the outside world of objects. He destroys the
encapsulation of the airtight castle of the knowing subject.
51
BT, 62/89
Chapter Two: Foucault’s Critique of SubjectificationSubjectivity and Truth Effect
Throughout the extensive body of work of Foucault, he has dedicated himself to probing
the multifaceted discussions inherent in the concept of subject, as elucidated in his article, The
Subject and Power, where he articulates, “my objective, instead, has been to create a history of
the different modes by which, in our culture, human beings are made subjects.”
1
This exploration is segmented into three distinct directions. Firstly, in The Order of
Things, Foucault investigates how humans are shaped into speaking subjects within linguistics or
philology, become laboring subjects within the economic sphere, and are simply living subjects
within the domain of biology. The second trajectory he pursues emerges in his studies such as
The History of Madness, and Discipline and Punish, where he scrutinizes how humans are
segmented based on various criteriasuch as the division between the mad and the lucid, the
categorization of criminals and the virtuous. According to Foucault, this process of division
simultaneously objectifies individuals and transforms them into subjects. Finally, in The History
of Sexuality, Foucault examines how humans actively construct themselves as subjects. As he
elucidates, the evolution of sexual knowledge engenders the categorization of individuals
according to the paradigms established by such knowledge, thus prompting them to identify as
particular subjects of sexuality. Notably, Foucault's later work witnesses a pivotal shift often
referred to as "the ethical turn," wherein he conceptualizes the subject as a reflexive relationship
individuals maintain with themselves. This introspective dimension underscores Foucault's
evolving engagement with the multifaceted nature of subjectivity.
1
Michel Foucault, “The Subject and Power,” Critical Inquiry 8, no. 4 (July 1, 1982): 777,
https://doi.org/10.1086/448181.
In this thesis, my focus revolves around the critical examination of subjectivity by
Foucault and Heidegger. Originating from Descartes, the central concern in the history of
Western philosophy pertains to understanding how, as knowing subjects, we acquire true
knowledge of the world. The exploration of subjectivity is approached from an epistemological
perspective. Heidegger traces the metaphysical root of the concept of the subject. Foucault
however approached the problem of subjectivity from a different angle. He diverges from the
customary approach to questioning the relation between subjectivity and true knowledge,
prompting an inquiry into the effects of purported true knowledge on subjectivity and its
influence on self-experience. This chapter aims to delineate Foucault's unique perspective in
critically studying the concept of the subject within the social realm, with a specific focus on his
analysis in the first volume of The History of Sexuality. The emphasis will be on Foucault's
elucidation of the process of subjectification through his examination of the science of sexuality.
In his discussion of the concept of the subject, Foucault articulates two distinct meanings,
as elucidated in The Subject and Power
2
. In one sense, being a subject implies being subjugated
to a particular power system. In another sense, subjectivity involves being shaped by a specific
identity through self-knowledge mediated by external knowledge. For Foucault, these dual
processes mutually reinforce each other and coalesce. This interconnectedness is notably evident
in Foucault’s analysis of the science of sexuality, when he explicates how humans are made
subjects of sexuality through “power-knowledge.The latter is a term created by Foucault to
denote the reciprocal processes in which power and knowledge influence each other mutually but
also in which each actively utilizes the other. In the subsequent analysis, I will illustrate the
interrelation between the process of subjectification and the process of objectification.
2
Foucault, “The Subject and Power, 781.
Furthermore, I will explore how these two processes converge in the truth game propelled by
power-knowledge. According to Foucault, the truth game is “a set of rules by which truth is
produced.”
3
That is, for Foucault, truth is not about the absolute truth, but more about the
mechanism of producing truth intertwined with power relations. Finally, I will delve into how the
dynamic interplay between subjectification and objectification, manifested in the truth game,
shapes our identity and produces effects on our subjectivity.
In Foucault’s analysis of The History of Sexuality, there are three aspects of
subjectification. Firstly, the incitement mechanism of discourses leads the speaking subject to
become aware of themselves as the subject of desire, lust, and pleasure. At the same time, these
subjects undergo scientific study, specification, and classification, consequently becoming
objects of knowledge concerning sexualitythus undergoing a process of objectification. This is
also where subjectification and objectification reinforce each other. Lastly, through exhaustive
scrutiny and scientific investigation, the knowledge and “truth” of sexuality claim to reveal
insights about human beings. Individuals internalize these truths, shaping their self-knowledge
and becoming tethered to specific identities.
Concerning the initial aspect of subjectification, the practices designed to make
individuals aware that they are subjects of pleasure and desire are implemented and executed
through discourse. Foucault observed an interesting phenomenon, namely, that starting from 18
th
century, reality deviates from what the traditional repressive hypothesis describes. Contrary to
expectations that discussions about sex would decrease due to increased censorship and silencing
policies, quite the opposite, there was an explosion of discourses about sex. As for the repressive
3
Michel Foucault, “The Ethics of the Concern for Self as Practice of Freedom,” in Ethics Subjectivity and Truth ;
the Essential Works of Michael Foucault, 1954-1984, ed. James D. Faubion, 2000, 297,
https://philpapers.org/rec/FOUESA-2.
hypothesis, it presents a historical interpretation that views power as exclusively repressive and
regards the advocacy for sexual "liberation" as transcending this repressive power structure. The
hypothesis is, further, that sexuality was “repressed” during the Victorian era and thereafter,
into the 20
th
century period in which Foucault was writing. However, Foucault’s objections note
that despite stringent prohibitions on specific words and subtler limitations on when and where
certain topics could be discussed, there were notable interests from the side of power, and the
afore-mentioned explosion of “scientific” discourses on “sexuality.” Government, university, and
medical bodies sought explicit enunciation and exhaustive details in policy, discussions,
scholarship, and clinical practices concerning sex. This phenomenon coincided with the
invention of the term “population,” which became a pivotal economic and political factor for a
state. With variables like birth rate, fertility, health status, and life expectancy being critical to
human resource and labor capacity, sex assumed a central role in all these factors. Consequently,
it became imperative to discuss and manage sex for the collective welfare and administer it for
greater utility. As a result, not only has every action to be spoken about, but every thought, every
image in mind, every delectation, and every desire has to be articulated. Transforming all these
subtle insinuations into discourses has two effects. Firstly, it awakens and intensifies people’s
awareness about their thoughts, desires and pleasures. Furthermore, through the practice of
openly discussing everything, the speaking subject at the same time becomes aware of their
being the subject of desire, lust and pleasure. This constitutes the first meaning of
subjectificationan acknowledgement that there must be a subject to whom all these subtle
psychological movements can be attributed. Every thought, feeling and elapsing imagination has
to be traced back to a subject which should be responsible for them. Individuals are not merely
engaging in actions; they are now required to be aware and cautious that they are subjects of
desire.
The second facet of subjectification that warrants discussion involves the process of
constructing sexuality as a “form” of science and subsequently treating humans as objects of
scientific knowledge. It is crucial to note that the process of subjectification is often intertwined
with objectification, with the two processes reinforcing each other. Before diving into the
discussion about the process of subjectification in the realm of science of sexuality, I have to
give a clear account of sex and sexuality in Foucault’s system. This interconnectedness is
particularly evident in the realm of the science of sexuality, where humans and human sexuality
are treated as objects of investigation and scientific study. Participation in the inquiry of
sexuality, conducted through clinical conversations, questionnaires, and interactive
interrogations, not only subjects individuals to scientific scrutiny but also makes them self-
conscious of their role as subjects of their sexuality. Looking back at history, Foucault highlights
the beginning of the 19
th
century as a period when various domains increasingly focused on and
incited discourses about sex. For instance, medicine approached the topic in terms of disorders of
the nervous system, and psychiatry explored its connection with mental illness. Criminal justice,
extending beyond its traditional focus on heinous sex crimes, broadened its scope to include
minor offences and indecencies. Particularly noteworthy is the establishment of Scientia
Sexualis, transforming the traditional confessional ritual from the pastoral Christian context into
the scientific inquiry into the truth of sexuality.
As Foucault indicates, scientia sexualis, firstly, transforms traditional confessional
procedures into clinical steps aimed at inducing discourses. This includes incorporating
confession into the examination process, blending personal narratives with identifiable indicators
and manifestations, and utilizing methods such as interrogation, meticulous questioning,
hypnosis, memory recall, and free association. All of these approaches serve to reintroduce the
act of confession into a realm characterized by scientifically valid observations. Secondly,
scientia sexualis assumes a broad and diffuse causality, suggesting that sex can be the reason for
various outcomes. This assumption is pivotal in transforming traditional confession into the
science of sexuality. It suggests that every subtle aspect of one’s sexual conduct can be causally
linked to different results in one’s existence. This, I contend, is the crux of transforming
traditional confession into the science of sexuality. By establishing the assumption that sex
possesses explanatory power, rationality is extended to human sexuality. This trend of
rationalization applied to the human body, desire and sex, is intimately tied to knowledge. The
process of rationalization initially attempts to elucidate these mysterious causal connections. To
understand them, individuals must turn themselves into objects of knowledge, investigating the
causal factors within sex and themselves to comprehend everything that transpired in their
existence. Simultaneously, this assumption about the causal power of sexuality serves as a
crucial justification for incorporating exhaustive interrogation of old confessions into the modern
scientific study of sexuality. Thirdly, it assumes the latent nature of sexuality, embedding the
coercive essence of confession into scientific inquiry. Fourthly, the scientia sexualis necessitates
interpretation. In other words, not only is a speaker required, but a listener is equally
indispensable. The listener, in this context, plays a crucial role in elucidating and interpreting the
speaker’s discourse, effectively transforming the discourse about sex into signs awaiting
decipherment. Upon reflection on the listener's role, it becomes evident that, in the binary
relationship between the speaker and the listener, the listener holds greater significance. They
wield the power to assign meaning to the speaker's discourse, determining the truth of the
discourse. In essence, the truth of the discourse lies with the interpreter, i.e., the listener.
This realization prompts us to consider the nature of this truth more deeply. Is this truth
akin to the neutral, objective truth or is it, as per Foucault's conception, a truth game? The latter
is not about uncovering an objective truth but rather adheres to rules governing how a person can
articulate a certain matter, based on distinctions between truth and falsehood. This dynamic also
creates an opportunity for power relations to subtly influence the production of knowledge and
truth concerning sexuality. It introduces an element of uncertainty into the science of sexuality,
making the process of producing truth related to subjectification problematic, given its
connection to the power regime. These issues and criticisms related to subjectification connected
with power relations will be addressed in the next section. Finally, the act of telling the truth is
endowed with the "medical" power of recovery. When everything is articulated, the truth is
unearthed, and this initiates a healing process akin to the redemptive effect of confession. Telling
the truth is seen as having a "medical" effect. Psychoanalysis enters the discourse precisely at
this intersection: serving as both a theory highlighting the intrinsic connection between law and
desire, and a method for mitigating the repercussions of taboo where its strict enforcement
proves detrimental. In practical application, psychoanalysis undertook the task of ameliorating
the consequences of repression, which the prohibition could induce, enabling individuals to
articulate their incestuous desires openly.
All these factors have facilitated the transformation of confession, embedding it into the
scientific study of sexuality. However, we have to examine the scientificity of the scientific study
of sexuality, as Foucault indicates that by presenting itself in a unitary fashion, as anatomy and
lack, as function and latency, as instinct and meaning, it was able to mark the line of contact
between a knowledge of human sexuality and the biological sciences of reproduction; thus,
without really borrowing anything from these sciences, excepting a few doubtful analogies, the
knowledge of sexuality gained through proximity a guarantee of quasi-scientificity.
4
To be
more precise, sexuality is a historical construction for Foucault. That is, it is constructed by
power interplaying with knowledge. Foucault gave several examples of how sexuality is
constructed. One example he termed the “hysterization of women’s bodies,” which has led to the
perception of women as primarily sexed beings as well as a fount of medical work on human
reproduction. Another influential concept is the “pedagogization of children’s sex,” which
characterizes children as possessing significant sexual agency and aims to shape that behavior.
Indeed, this heightened perception of children's sexuality was often seen as perilous,
necessitating vigilant monitoring and regulation. Additionally, the “socialization of procreative
behavior” serves as another nexus of knowledge and power, emphasizing reproduction as a
pivotal societal concern. Correspondingly, the notion of sex as an outcome of sexuality is a
historical construct, inherently subservient to the broader concept of sexuality. By introducing
the conceptual construct of “sex,” the deployment of sexuality established one of its fundamental
internal mechanisms: “the desire for sex-the desire to have it, to have access to it, to discover it,
to liberate it, to articulate it in discourse, to formulate it in truth.”
5
This shift prompts individuals to be more cautious and self-aware about being subjects of
sex. Moreover, sex is established as a significant causal factor, possessing the power to explain
the mysteries within human existence and shed light on our own truth as humans. This act
essentially rendered “sex” itself as something desirable. Consequently, it is this allure of sex that
4
Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality: An Introduction (New York : Pantheon Books, 1978), 155.
5
Foucault, The History of Sexuality: An Introduction, 156.
binds each individual to the imperative to understand it, to uncover its regularity and its potency.
We, as subjects of sex, treat ourselves as objects of scientific study, unveiling the latent truth
about ourselves. This interconnection and reinforcement of subjectification and objectification
are exemplified through the process of the science of sexuality. This process of subjectification
intertwined with the process of objectification made the subject qua subject finally become the
object of knowledge which is crucial for exemplifying how the truth game works within the
interconnection of these two processes. And it is this allure that often leads us to believe we are
championing the right of our own sex against all forms of power, but in reality, we are intricately
entwined tighter with the deployment of sexuality.
The third facet of subjectification involves the dividing process, which is linked to the
objectification of humans. This connection arises due to the increasing concern about population
for a state. Matters related to sex, encompassing fertility, birth rate, and life expectancy, capture
public interest. To manage sexual activities and channel them towards the productive
reproduction of human resources and labor capacity for a country, during the 19th century, the
public attention moves from conjugal sexuality to encompass all other sexualities outside of
marriage. The medical studies engaged in the complex landscape of sexualities, empowered by
the operation of power, go beyond mere prohibition. To further expound on the studies of
peripheral sexualities during the 19th century, Foucault references the psychological study of
homosexuality initiated by Westphal’s article, "Contrary Sexual Sensations."
6
A notable observation by Foucault is that the characterization and definition of
homosexuality do not rely on external relations but rather focus on the inner sensibility of an
individual. This internal reversion of defining the individual is noteworthy. Homosexuality is no
6
Foucault, The History of Sexuality: An Introduction, 43.
longer defined solely by the external relationships of the person involved or by acts. Instead, it is
explored inwardly, tracing every psychological trait and sensibility. This shift is particularly
significant; starting from this point, homosexuality transforms from being a form of relationship
to becoming a distinct identity connected to an individual's inner features. This transformation
gains added importance when considering Foucault's observation that defined by ancient civil
codes, sodomy was simply an action forbidden, with the person facing no more than punishment
for the deed. Foucault highlights the shift in focus under the science of sexuality, where
individuals are scrutinized for their inner psychological changes, sensibilities, fleeting thoughts,
imaginations, and memories. Homosexuality evolves into an identity representing one's past,
history, and even childhood. A once forbidden action is now reversed and internalized as the
insidious and fundamental trait of the individual, becoming the indelible stamp on one's identity.
While sodomy was seen as a certain temporary and often one-time aberrant action,
homosexuality has evolved into a recognized aspect of human identity, representing a distinctive
group of people.
In addition to homosexuality, various minor peripheral aberrations are assigned names,
akin to entomological classifications, through psychological, psychiatric, and medical studies.
Examples include “mixoscopophiles, gynecomasts, presbyophiles, sexoesthetic inverts, and
dyspareunist women.”
7
This categorization stands in stark contrast to the repressive hypothesis,
which suggests the exclusion and elimination of such peripheral aberrations. Instead, they are
meticulously examined, categorized, and specified. The power regime does not seek to silence
these peripheral sexual behaviors that are not geared towards procreation. Contrary to being
overlooked by the law, these behaviors are now given names and elevated to the status of
7
Foucault, The History of Sexuality: An Introduction, 43.
scientific realities that articulate the essence or nature of the individuals involved. This
comprehensive spectrum tries to ground itself on different analytical, scientific, and enduring
realities to be considered fundamental principles of comprehension and categorization. No longer
neglected by the law, science, or society, a more stringent regime is in place, bringing all other
peripheral sexualities under close supervision. This aligns precisely with the third facet of
subjectification: the plan or tactic behind disseminating this knowledge and specifying these
peripheral sexualities through the machinery of power is to scatter or embed them throughout the
real world, integrating them into an individual's life or experience. Essentially, the objective is to
weave these elements into an individual's reality, consequently influencing how people perceive
themselves, construct their self-knowledge, and shape their identity.
Chapter Three: The Mathematical in Heidegger and the Cartesian Moment in Foucault
Based on the examination of Heidegger and Foucault’s respective analyses and critiques
of subjectivity in the first two chapters, it appears challenging to identify common ground
between the two. However, starting with a nuanced exploration of the meaning of presence-at-
hand in Being and Truth, Heidegger tries to give an account and evaluation of modern
metaphysics. By approaching Heidegger’s critique of the Cartesian subject from this perspective,
I unveil intriguing parallels with Foucault’s critical analysis of subjectification in his endevor to
elucidate the history of subjectivity and truth from the lens of emphasizing the interplay between
the care of self and knowledge of self throughout the history of philosophy.
In Being and Truth, the concept of presence-at-hand intricately intertwines with the term
"mathematical." Heidegger traces the origin of the termthe mathematical to the Greek word
"μαθήματα," denoting what can be taught and comprehended in the preeminent sense. To
elaborate further, the mathematical encompasses knowledge that can be imparted to an
individual in a way that they can comprehend independently based on their innate capabilities,
which is what "the preeminent" means. It resembles the kind of knowledge "recalled" by
Menoan understanding that can be independently grasped and known from within. Another
layer of the meaning of the mathematical, particularly in terms of its definitionwhat can be
taught and received in the preeminent sense, involves a self-contained process of knowledge
formation. In this sense, the mathematical possesses its own inference principles, generating the
objects to be known and making its progress independently. As for presence-at-hand, it
constitutes the content of the mathematical within this framework. That is, conforming to the
meaning of the mathematical and serving as the objects of the mathematical, presence-at-hand
refers to something that is both elementary and unequivocally perspicuous. In other words, it
denotes something that is fully disclosed to us, fitting our innate cognitive processes and
allowing for straightforward comprehension through common sense and intuition.
When Heidegger delves into Descartes's process of doubt, he emphasizes that methodical
doubt functions as an expression of the mathematical conception of method. This doubt
systematically eliminates everything that lacks perspicuity and simplicity, leaving only the act of
doubting itself and the "I" engaged in doubting as unequivocally straightforward and evident.
The Cartesian "I" precisely embodies the defining features of presence-at-hand, being "known
and cognized as such."
1
This resonance of Cartesian “I” with the objects of the mathematical
forms the basis for philosophy and all knowledge, a standpoint that Heidegger rejects. He warns
that the mathematical conception of method has predetermined the essential characteristics of the
philosophical foundation. Heidegger contends that, by adhering to the direction set by the
mathematical, the method through which philosophy poses questions and establishes its
grounding has become subservient to the mathematical method.
However, the primary concerns arising from the prevalence of the mathematical method
lie in the fact that the Cartesian "I," intricately connected to the human self, obstructs all avenues
to apprehend the Being of the self. When Descartes ultimately redirects the human self to
acknowledge the "I" as the sole certainty, this self-consciousness becomes the essence of the
human self, constituting its very Being. Yet, this shift distances us from genuine inquiry into
understanding the Being of the human self. The presence-at-hand of the thinking "I" carries the
1
Martin Heidegger, Being and Truth, trans. Gregory Fried and Richard Polt (Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 2016), 26.
characteristics of mathematical objectsbeing "point-like, ahistorical, and spiritless,"
2
which
Heidegger unequivocally deems non-essential to the Being of the human self. He argues that
considering Being-consciousness as the essence of the human self disregards "action, nor
decidedness, much less the characteristic of historicity and of man’s essential connection to those
who are being-here with him,"
3
elements that should be integral to the approach to the self. In
essence, the Cartesian subject, when equated with the self, fails to encapsulate aspects related to
human existence, such as their everyday life, interactions with others, and the experience of
living through time.
This critique of Heidegger draws certain parallels with Foucault’s reassessment of the so-
called “Cartesian moment” during his exploration of the history of subjectivity and truth.
Specifically, Foucault approaches this problem by examining the historical interplay between
“care of the self” (epimeleia heautou) and “know yourself” (gnōthi seauton). These are two
precepts originally derived from the Delphic precepts. In Hermeneutics of the Subject, Foucault
outlines his objective of investigating the historical dynamics between the subject and truth in the
history of Western philosophy, focusing particularly on these two precepts. He delves into the
reasons behind the inversion of the status of these two precepts in the philosophy of history.
Looking back to antiquity, Foucault highlights the significant role played by “care of the self.”
Starting with Socrates, who emphasizes the importance of “care of the self,” Foucault traces
similar emphasis in Stoic, Cynic and Epicurean philosophies. However, over time, this precept
becomes marginalized, eventually fading from collective memory. Foucault observes that know
yourself which presently holds a prominent position, has been subordinated to care of oneself.
2
Heidegger, Being and Truth, 34.
3
Ibid.
He notes, “the gnōthi seauton (‘know yourself’) appears quite clearly and again in a number of
significant texts, within the more general framework of the epimeleia heautou (care of the
oneself) as one of the forms, one of the consequences, as a sort of concrete, precise, and
particular application of the general rule: you must attend to yourself, you must not forget
yourself, you must take care of yourself.”
4
Given this historical context, in antiquity, "know yourself" consistently manifested as a
specific application of the more general principle of taking care of oneself, Foucault considers
the inversion of the roles of "care of self" and "know oneself" a significant question for inquiry.
He attributes this transformation to the "Cartesian moment" and emphasizes the impact of
Descartes's methodical doubt, akin to Heidegger’s perspective. Foucault discerns that Descartes's
methodical doubt has profound consequences in the history of philosophy, particularly in
reshaping the status of "care of self" and "know oneself." Foucault proclaims:
The Cartesian approach, which can be read quite explicitly in the Meditation, placed self-
evidence (l’évidence) at the origin, the point of departure of the philosophical approach
self-evidence as it appears, that is to say as it is given, as it is actually given to
consciousness without any possible doubt. The Cartesian approach [therefore] refers to
knowledge of the self, as a form of consciousness at least. What's more, by putting the
self-evidence of the subject's own existence at the very source of access to being, this
knowledge of oneself (no longer in the form of the test of self-evidence, but in the form
of the impossibility of doubting my existence as subject) made the "know yourself" into a
fundamental means of access to truth.
5
4
Michel Foucault et al., The Hermeneutics of the Subject : Lectures at the Collège De France, 1981-1982, 2005, 4,
http://ci.nii.ac.jp/ncid/BA7349179X.
5
Heidegger, Being and Truth, 14.
The perspective articulated in this statement originates from Foucault's investigation into
the marginalization of "the care of the self" in the history of Western philosophy. While it may
seem like a departure from Heidegger's examination of Western metaphysics, Foucault
demonstrates a familiarity with Heidegger's terms. Foucault underscores that the question of
being is shaped by the self-consciousness of the Cartesian "I." Through the process of doubt, the
Cartesian "I" emerges as the sole indubitable and perspicuous reality, laying the foundation for
all other existences. In parallel with Heidegger’s insights, Foucault notes that our knowledge of
ourselves is determined by the unquestionable perspicuousness of the Cartesian "I," where "I"
signifies the self. Uttering “I” inherently refers back to ourselves, and this self-aware "I" as the
thinking entity ultimately becomes the essential being of the self. While Heidegger critiques the
notion that the being of the self is determined by self-consciousness, Foucault is similarly
dissatisfied with the idea that our understanding of the self is equated solely with this self-
evident existence as the Cartesian subject. Now, with the Cartesian subject representing the self
and serving as the certain ground for all knowledge (i.e., the Cartesian moment), "know
yourself" is elevated to the forefront as the path to truth.
Dominance of the mathematical versus spirituality and philosophy
Heidegger places a paramount emphasis on the question of Being and beings as the
fundamental concern in philosophy. Although Foucault directs his attention towards the history
of truth, both philosophers scrutinize the impact of the Cartesian method on the trajectory of
these philosophical investigations throughout the history of Western philosophy. An
understanding of the significance of presence-at-hand within the context of the mathematical
unveils a new dimension in Heidegger's critique of the Cartesian subject. This, in turn, allows us
to establish connections with Foucault's reassessment of the Cartesian moment in his exploration
of the history of subjectivity and truth. As Heidegger contends that the Cartesian “I” as the
indubitable presence-at-hand exactly represents the predominance of mathematical conception of
method in modern metaphysics, Foucault also detects that the Cartesian moment opens a new era
that spiritualitythe major theme of philosophizing in Hellenistic philosophyis completely
left behind. Consequently, the relationship between subjectivity and truth undergoes a
fundamental transformation.
By questioning why the foundation for philosophy and all knowledge must be something
inherently simple and perspicuous as something present at hand, Heidegger sheds light on the
mathematical method's influence on constructing a metaphysical system. This method, akin to
mathematics, commences with something present-at-handknowable through intuitionand
then follows its deductive laws to generate further propositions. Heidegger asserts that Descartes
endeavors to construct philosophy through this methodical approach, concluding that not only is
the outer structure of the metaphysical system determined by the mathematical, but its inner
content is also dictated by mathematical principles.
In a similar vein, Foucault delineates the distinction between philosophy and spirituality.
According to Foucault, philosophy is a mode of thinking that explores the conditions allowing an
individual to attain truth. It seeks to identify the boundaries for gaining truth. To be concise,
philosophy cares about the conditions of the subject in terms of gaining the truth. Conversely,
spirituality, according to Foucault, focuses on the effect of truth and the self-transformation
necessary to get access to the truth. Foucault highlights three features of spirituality: firstly, the
subject, in its current state, lacks access to truth; secondly, the price of truth lies in the
transformation of the subject's being; finally, truth always yields a rewarding effect on the
subject's existence. Foucault emphasizes the inherent connection between spirituality and
philosophy. However, the Cartesian moment introduces the idea that to attain truth, no changes
are needed in the self. Based on the self-evidence of the Cartesian "I," nothing needs to be known
or altered about the self. Starting from the ground of indubitable Cartesian I for all knowledge,
there are only requirements contained within the knowledge and extrinsic requirements for an
individual to attain truth. Foucault proclaims,
I think the modern age of the history of truth begins when knowledge itself and
knowledge alone gives access to the truth. That is to say, it is when the philosopher (or
the scientist, or simply someone who seeks the truth) can recognize the truth and have
access to it himself and solely through his activity of knowing, without anything else
being demanded of him and without him having to change or alter his being as subject.
6
That is, as a subject aiming to acquire truth, one only needs to adhere to formal
conditions such as objective criteria and methodological rules required by the internal features of
knowledge, coupled with external factors like education, diligence, and honesty. None of these
requirements necessitates a transformation of the subject’s being, which breaks up the
connection between spirituality and philosophy.
Foucault points out, “when the subject's being is not put into question by the necessity of
having access to the truth, I think we have entered a different age of the history of relations
between subjectivity and truth.”
7
In this new age, the emphasis shifts solely to knowledge as the
gateway to truth, leaving spirituality behind and fundamentally altering the relationship between
6
Michel Foucault, The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1981-1982, ed. Frédéric
Gros, trans. Graham Burchell (New York: Picador, 2005), 17.
7
Foucault et al., The Hermeneutics of the Subject : Lectures at the Collège De France, 1981-1982, 18.
subjectivity and truth. Now, starting from this new age, knowledge can develop itself as long as
it is following its own law of development leaving the care about the being and structure of the
subject all behind. Subjectivity is divorced from truth in such a way that there is no more
rewarding effect of truth for the subject and the being of the subject is not transformed or
enlightened by the attainment of truth. There are no more mutual, flowing, recursive interactions
between the subject and truth. Subject do not change its mode of being to gain truth, and there is
no rebound effect on subject’s being. Knowledge now unfolds and develops itself according to
its own internal logic. The subject is only the participants of the development of knowledge
which will extend into the limitless realm of advancement, with an unknown culmination. The
benefits of gaining truth now are exemplified through the accumulation of knowledge, which
will only become apparent over time through the gradual construction of various fields of
knowledge, or the psychological and social advantages gained from the diligent pursuit and
discovery of truth.
However, in this new era, the focus shifts away from the Being of the subject, as Foucault
concludes, “the truth cannot save the subject.”
8
This sentiment echoes Heidegger’s critique of
modern metaphysics, particularly its adherence to the mathematical method and his criticism of
the new beginning of philosophy as a further decline that veers philosophy away from its
fundamental question about Being and beings. Foucault's analysis of the relationship between
subjectivity and truth mirrors a Heideggerian concern about the Being and structure of the
subject, bridging the gap between the two thinkers. Moreover, their examination of the Cartesian
approach, viewed through the historical lens of the history of metaphysics and the history of truth
and subjectivity respectively, also illuminates their shared concerns and similarities.
8
Foucault et al., The Hermeneutics of the Subject : Lectures at the Collège De France, 1981-1982, 19.
Bibliography:
Descartes, René. The Principles of Philosophy. Translated by Jonathan Bennett. Charlottesville,
VA: InteLex, n.d.
Dreyfus, Hubert L. Being-in-the-world: A commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, Division
I. Cambridge. Mass. USA: MIT Press, 2009.
Foucault, Michel. “The Ethics of the Concern for Self as Practice of Freedom.” In Ethics
Subjectivity and Truth ; the Essential Works of Michael Foucault, 1954-1984, edited by
James D. Faubion, New York: The New Press, 2000. https://philpapers.org/rec/FOUESA-
2.
———. The History of Sexuality: An Introduction. New York : Pantheon Books, 1978.
———. “The Subject and Power.” Critical Inquiry 8, no. 4 (July 1, 1982): 77795.
https://doi.org/10.1086/448181.
———. The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1981-1982. Edited
by Frédéric Gros. Translated by Graham Burchell . New York: Picador, 2005.
Heidegger, Martin, Edited by Gregory Fried, and Polt Richard F H. “Chapter Two: The System
of Modern Metaphysics and the First of Its Primary Determining Grounds: The
Mathematical.” Essay. In Being and Truth. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2016.
Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Translated by John Macquarrie & Edward Robinson.
London, SCM Press: Basil Blackwell, 1962.
King, Magda, and John Llewellyn. A guide to Heidegger’s Being and Time. Albany: State
University of New York Press, 2001.
Shockey, R. Matthew. “Heidegger’s Descartes and Heidegger’s Cartesianism.” European
Journal of Philosophy 20, no. 2 (2010): 285311. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-
0378.2010.00408.x.
Zimmerman, Michael E. Eclipse of the Self: The Development of Heidegger’s Concept of
Authenticity. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press, 1986.
Çüçen, A. Kadir. “Heidegger’s Reading of Descartes’ Dualism.” The Paideia Archive: Twentieth
World Congress of Philosophy, 1998, 5764. https://doi.org/10.5840/wcp20-
paideia19986134.